Demanding that a theory is falsifiable or observable, without any subtlety, will hold science back. We need madcap ideas
The Viennese physicist Wolfgang Pauli suffered from a guilty conscience. He’d solved one of the knottiest puzzles in nuclear physics, but at a cost. ‘I have done a terrible thing,’ he admitted to a friend in the winter of 1930. ‘I have postulated a particle that cannot be detected.’
Despite his pantomime of despair, Pauli’s letters reveal that he didn’t really think his new sub-atomic particle would stay unseen. He trusted that experimental equipment would eventually be up to the task of proving him right or wrong, one way or another. Still, he worried he’d strayed too close to transgression. Things that were genuinely unobservable, Pauli believed, were anathema to physics and to science as a whole.
Pauli’s views persist among many scientists today. It’s a basic principle of scientific practice that a new theory shouldn’t invoke the undetectable. Rather, a good explanation should be falsifiable – which means it ought to rely on some hypothetical data that could, in principle, prove the theory wrong. These interlocking standards of falsifiability and observability have proud pedigrees: falsifiability goes back to the mid-20th-century philosopher of science Karl Popper, and observability goes further back than that. Today they’re patrolled by self-appointed guardians, who relish dismissing some of the more fanciful notions in physics, cosmology and quantum mechanics as just so many castles in the sky. The cost of allowing such ideas into science, say the gatekeepers, would be to clear the path for all manner of manifestly unscientific nonsense.
But for a theoretical physicist, designing sky-castles is just part of the job. Spinning new ideas about how the world could be – or in some cases, how the world definitely isn’t – is central to their work. Some structures might be built up with great care over many years, and end up with peculiar names such as inflationary multiverse or superstring theory. Others are fabricated and dismissed casually over the course of a single afternoon, found and lost again by a lone adventurer in the troposphere of thought.
That doesn’t mean it’s just freestyle sky-castle architecture out there at the frontier. The goal of scientific theory-building is to understand the nature of the world with increasing accuracy over time. All that creative energy has to hook back onto reality at some point. But turning ingenuity into fact is much more nuanced than simply announcing that all ideas must meet the inflexible standards of falsifiability and observability. These are not measures of the quality of a scientific theory. They might be neat guidelines or heuristics, but as is usually the case with simple answers, they’re also wrong, or at least only half-right.
Falsifiability doesn’t work as a blanket restriction in science for the simple reason that there are no genuinely falsifiable scientific theories. I can come up with a theory that makes a prediction that looks falsifiable, but when the data tell me it’s wrong, I can conjure some fresh ideas to plug the hole and save the theory.
The history of science is full of examples of this ex post facto intellectual engineering. In 1781, William and Caroline Herschel discovered the planet Uranus. Physicists of the time promptly set about predicting its orbit using Sir Isaac Newton’s law of universal gravitation. But in the following decades, as astronomers followed Uranus’s motion in its slow 84-year orbit around the Sun, they noticed that something was wrong. Uranus didn’t quite move as it should. Puzzled, they refined their measurements, took more and more careful observations, but the anomaly didn’t go away. Newton’s physics simply didn’t predict the location of Uranus over time.
But astronomers of the day didn’t claim that the unexpected data falsified Newtonian gravity. Instead, they proposed another explanation for the strange motion of Uranus: something large and unseen was tugging on the planet. Calculations showed that it would have to be another planet, as large as Uranus and even farther from the Sun. In 1846, the French astrophysicist Urbain Le Verrier predicted the location of this hypothetical planet. Unable to get any French observatories interested in the hunt, he sent the details of his prediction to colleagues in Germany. That night, they pointed their telescopes where Le Verrier had told them to look, and within half an hour they spotted the planet Neptune. Newtonian physics, rather than being falsified, had been fabulously vindicated – it had successfully predicted the exact location of an entire unseen planet.
For years, the mystery of Mercury was unsolved, without any suggestion that Newton was wrong
Flush with success, Le Verrier went after another planetary puzzle. Several years after his discovery of Neptune, it became clear to him and other astronomers that Mercury wasn’t moving as it was supposed to, either. The point in its orbit where it made its closest approach to the Sun, known as the perihelion, shifted a little more than Newton’s gravity said it should each Mercurial year, adding up to 43 extra arcseconds (a unit of angular measurement) over the course of a century. This is a tiny amount – less than one-30,000th of a full orbit around the Sun – but just as with Uranus before, the anomaly didn’t go away with persistent observation. It stubbornly remained, defying the ghost of Newton.
Once again, Newtonian gravity was not thrown out as falsified – at least, not immediately. Instead, Le Verrier tried the same trick again: pinning the anomaly on an unseen planet, a tiny rock so close to the Sun that it had been missed by all other astronomers throughout human history. He called the planet Vulcan, after the Roman god of the forge. Le Verrier and others sought Vulcan for years, lugging powerful telescopes to solar eclipses in an attempt to catch a glimpse of the unseen planet in the brief minutes of totality while the Sun was blocked by the Earth’s moon.
Le Verrier never found Vulcan. After his death in 1877, the astronomy community gave up the search, concluding that Vulcan simply wasn’t there. But even so, Newton’s gravity wasn’t discarded. Instead, astronomers of the time collectively shrugged and moved on. For years, the mystery of Mercury’s perihelion was unsolved, without any serious suggestion that Newton was wrong. Falsification was simply not on the menu.
Finally, in 1915, Albert Einstein used his brand-new theory of general relativity to show that he could succeed where Le Verrier had failed. General relativity was a new account of how gravity worked, superseding Newtonian physics – and it perfectly predicted the shift in the perihelion of Mercury. Einstein said he was ‘beside himself with joy’ when he realised that his theory could correctly solve this longstanding puzzle. Four years later, the British astronomer Arthur Eddington and his team took their powerful telescopes to an eclipse, not to hunt for Vulcan, but to confirm that starlight bent around the Sun as Einstein’s theory had predicted. They found that general relativity was right (though later investigations suggested that their results were marred by errors, despite reaching the correct conclusion); Einstein was instantly rocketed to fame as the man who had shown Newton wrong.
So Newtonian gravity was ultimately thrown out, but not merely in the face of data that threatened it. That wasn’t enough. It wasn’t until a viable alternative theory arrived, in the form of Einstein’s general relativity, that the scientific community entertained the notion that Newton might have missed a trick. But what if Einstein had never shown up, or had been incorrect? Could astronomers have found another way to account for the anomaly in Mercury’s motion? Certainly – they could have said that Vulcan was there after all, and was merely invisible to telescopes in some way.
This might sound somewhat far-fetched, but again, the history of science demonstrates that this kind of thing actually happens, and it sometimes works – as Pauli found out in 1930. At the time, new experiments threatened one of the core principles of physics, known as the conservation of energy. The data showed that in a certain kind of radioactive decay, electrons could fly out of an atomic nucleus with a range of speeds (and attendant energies) – even though the total amount of energy in the reaction should have been the same each time. That meant energy sometimes went missing from these reactions, and it wasn’t clear what was happening to it.
The Danish physicist Niels Bohr was willing to give up energy conservation. But Pauli wasn’t ready to concede the idea was dead. Instead, he came up with his outlandish particle. ‘I have hit upon a desperate remedy to save … the energy theorem,’ he wrote. The new particle could account for the loss of energy, despite having almost no mass and no electric charge. But particle detectors at the time had no way of seeing a chargeless particle, so Pauli’s proposed solution was invisible.
Nonetheless, rather than agreeing with Bohr that energy conservation had been falsified, the physics community embraced Pauli’s hypothetical particle: what came to be known as a ‘neutrino’ (the little neutral one), once the Italian physicist Enrico Fermi refined the theory a few years later. The happy epilogue was that neutrinos were finally observed in 1956, with technology that had been totally unforeseen a quarter-century earlier: a new kind of particle detector deployed in conjunction with a nuclear reactor. Pauli’s ghostly particles were real; in fact, later work revealed that trillions of neutrinos from the Sun pass through our body every second, totally unnoticed and unobserved.
So invoking the invisible to save a theory from falsification is sometimes the right scientific move. Yet Pauli certainly didn’t believe that his particle could never be observed. He hoped that it could be seen eventually, and he was right. Similarly, Einstein’s general relativity was vindicated through observation. Falsification just can’t be the answer, or at least not the whole answer, to the question of what makes a good theory. What about observability?
It’s certainly true that observation plays a crucial role in science. But this doesn’t mean that scientific theories have to deal exclusively in observable things. For one, the line between the observable and unobservable is blurry – what was once ‘unobservable’ can become ‘observable’, as the neutrino shows. Sometimes, a theory that postulates the imperceptible has proven to be the right theory, and is accepted as correct long before anyone devises a way to see those things.
Take the debate within physics in the second half of the 1800s about atoms. Some scientists believed that they existed, but others were deeply skeptical. Physicists such as Ludwig Boltzmann in Austria, James Clerk Maxwell in the United Kingdom and Rudolf Clausius in Germany were convinced by the chemical and physical evidence that atomic theory was correct. Others, such as the Austrian physicist Ernst Mach, were unimpressed.
Atoms were unobservable. Thus Mach condemned them as unreal and unnecessary
To Mach, atoms were a wholly unnecessary hypothesis. After all, anything that wasn’t observable couldn’t be considered a part of a good scientific theory – in fact, such things couldn’t even be considered real. To him, the archetype for a perfect scientific theory was thermodynamics, the study of heat. This was a set of empirical laws relating directly observable quantities such as the temperature, pressure and volume of a gas. The theory was complete and perfect as it was, and made no reference to anything unobservable at all.
But Boltzmann, Maxwell and Clausius had worked hard to show that Mach’s beloved thermodynamics was far from complete. Over the course of the rest of the 19th century, they and others, such as the American scientist Josiah Willard Gibbs, proved that the entirety of thermodynamics – and then some – could be re-derived from the simple assumption that atoms were real, and that all objects in everyday life were composed of a phenomenal number of them. While it was impossible in practice to predict the behaviour of every individual atom, in aggregate their behaviour obeyed regular patterns – and because there are so many atoms in everyday objects (way more than 100 billion billion of them in a thimbleful of air), those patterns were never visibly broken, even though they were the result only of statistical tendencies, not ironclad laws.
The idea of demoting the laws of thermodynamics to mere patterns was repugnant to Mach; invoking things too small to be seen was even worse. ‘I don’t believe that atoms exist!’ he blurted out during a talk by Boltzmann in Vienna. Atoms were too small to see even with the most powerful microscope that could possibly be built at the time. Indeed, according to calculations carried out by Maxwell and the Austrian scientist Josef Loschmidt, atoms were hundreds of times smaller than the wavelength of visible light – and would thus be forever hidden from view of any microscope relying on light waves. Atoms were unobservable. Thus Mach condemned them as unreal and unnecessary, extraneous to the practice of science.
Mach’s views were enormously influential in his native Austria and elsewhere in central Europe. His ideas led his compatriot Boltzmann to despair of convincing the rest of the physics community that atoms were real; this might have contributed to Boltzmann’s suicide in 1906. Yet physicists who did subscribe to Mach’s ideas often found themselves stymied in their work. Walter Kaufmann, a talented German experimental physicist, found in 1897 that cathode rays (the kind of rays used inside old TVs and computer monitors) had a constant ratio of charge to mass. But rather than accepting that cathode rays might consist of small particles with a fixed charge and mass, he heeded Mach’s warning not to postulate anything unobservable, and remained silent on the subject. Months later, the English physicist JJ Thomson found the same curious fact about cathode rays. But Mach’s views were less popular in England, and Thomson was comfortable suggesting the existence of a tiny particle that comprised cathode rays. He called it the electron, and won the Nobel Prize for its discovery in 1906 (as well as an eternal place in all introductory physics and chemistry textbooks).
Mach’s ideas certainly weren’t all bad; his writing inspired the young Einstein in his early work on relativity. Mach’s influence also extended to his godson, Pauli, the child of two fellow intellectuals in Vienna. Mach’s ideas played a major role in Pauli’s early intellectual development, and the words of his godfather were probably ringing in Pauli’s ears when he first suggested the idea of the neutrino.
Unlike Pauli, Einstein was not afraid of suggesting unobservable things. In 1905, the same year he published his theory of special relativity, he proposed the existence of the photon, the particle of light, to an unbelieving world. (He was not proven right about photons for nearly 20 years.) Mach’s ideas also inspired a vital movement in philosophy a generation later, known as logical positivism – broadly speaking, the idea that the only meaningful statements about the world were ones that could be directly verified through observation. Positivism originated in Vienna and elsewhere in the 1920s, and the brilliant ideas of the positivists played a major role in shaping philosophy from that time to the present day.
But what makes something ‘observable’? Are things that can be seen only with specialised implements observable? Some of the positivists said the answer was no, only the unvarnished data of our senses would suffice – so things seen in microscopes were therefore not truly real. But in that case, ‘we cannot observe physical things through opera glasses, or even through ordinary spectacles, and one begins to wonder about the status of what we see through an ordinary windowpane,’ the philosopher Grover Maxwell wrote in 1962.
Furthermore, Maxwell pointed out that the definition of what was ‘unobservable in principle’ depends on our best scientific theories and full understanding of the world, and so moves over time. Before the invention of the telescope, for example, the idea of an instrument that could make distant objects appear closer seemed impossible; consequently, a planet too faint to be seen with the naked eye, such as Neptune, would have been deemed ‘unobservable in principle’. Yet Neptune is undoubtedly there – and we’ve not only seen it, we sent Voyager 2 there in 1989. Similarly, what we consider unobservable in principle today might become observable in the future with the advent of new physical theories and observational technologies. ‘It is theory, and thus science itself, which tells us what is or is not … observable,’ Maxwell wrote. ‘There are no a priori or philosophical criteria for separating the observable from the unobservable.’
We use all of it, the observable and the unobservable, when we do science
Even where theories propose identical observable outcomes, some are provisionally accepted while others are flatly rejected. Say I publish a theory stating that there are invisible microscopic unicorns with flowing hair, spiralled horns and a taste for partial differential equations; these unicorns are responsible for the randomness of the quantum world, pushing and pulling subatomic particles to ensure that they obey the Schrödinger equation, simply because they like that equation more than any other. This theory is, by its nature, totally observationally identical with quantum mechanics. But it is a profoundly silly theory, and would (I hope) be rejected by all physicists were someone to publish it.
Putting aside this glib example, the choices we make between observationally identical theories have a big impact upon the practice of science. The American physicist Richard Feynman pointed out that two wildly different theories that have identical observational consequences can still give you different perspectives on problems, and lead you to different answers and different experiments to conduct in order to discover the next theory. So it’s not just the observable content of our scientific theories that matters. We use all of it, the observable and the unobservable, when we do science. Certainly, we are more wary about our belief in the existence of invisible entities, but we don’t deny that the unobservable things exist, or at least that their existence is plausible.
Some of the most interesting scientific work gets done when scientists develop bizarre theories in the face of something new or unexplained. Madcap ideas must find a way of relating to the world – but demanding falsifiability or observability, without any sort of subtlety, will hold science back. It’s impossible to develop successful new theories under such rigid restrictions. As Pauli said when he first came up with the neutrino, despite his own misgivings: ‘Only those who wager can win.’
Leave a Reply